Transcript Slide 1

Linguistic Theory
Lecture 7
About Nothing
Nothing in grammar
• Language often contains irregular
paradigms where one or more expected
forms are absent
• E.g. English present tense verb agreement
1st
2nd
3rd
Singular
Am
Are
Is
plural
Are
Are
Are
– We see from the paradigm for be that number
and person play a role in determining the
form of the verb in the present tense:
• But other verbs do not show the same
pattern
1st
2nd
3rd
Singular
Smile
Smile
Smiles
Plural
Smile
Smile
Smile
• The only form which shows any agreement is
•
the 3rd person singular
Two choices:
– Assume that there is no verbal agreement except
for 3rd person singular and for 1st, 2nd and 3rd
person singular with the verb be
– Assume that there is a complete set of verbal
agreements, only most of them are realised by a
null morpheme
• The second choice is the one usually made as
it makes the system more regular
Other kinds of nothing
• Ellipsis
– She wanted to watch the TV, but I didn’t
– (want to watch the TV)
– * (take any notice)
• There is a difference:
– null morpheme = absent at the phonological level
– elliptical material = present at the semantic level
Nothing in the 1960s
• One possible way to treat ellipsis is as a
deletion:
– John drank beer and Bill wine
• John drank beer and Bill drank wine
• Deletions are recoverable:
– * John drank beer and Bill biscuits
• John drank beer and Bill ate biscuits
• This shows that ‘recoverability’ is a limited
notion:
– Recoverable from syntactic not pragmatic context
• A similar approach can account for the
following observations:
– The man [who I spoke to]
– The man [who I spoke to]
– He asked [who I spoke to]
– * He asked [who I spoke to]
• It is assumed that the same process is
•
•
involved in relative clause and interrogative
clause formation
But if so, why can the wh-relative delete but
not the wh-interrogative?
The wh-relative has an antecedent in the
noun that it modifies, so is recoverable. The
wh-interrogative does not and so is
unrecoverable.
Equi NP Deletion
• John wants [Bill to leave]
• Bill wants [to leave]
• Bill1 wants [Bill1 to leave]
• Equi-NP deletion:
In structures: ... NP1 ... NP1 ...
Delete the second NP
• But due to constraints on transformations,
deletion transformations fell out of favour
• Chomsky and Lasnik (1977) proposed that
instead of a deletion, ‘Equi’ structures
involve a phonologically null pronoun
(PRO):
• Bill1 wants [PRO1 to leave]
• PRO has two properties that need to be
accounted for:
– Its referential behaviour (control)
– Its distribution
Control
• Like most pronouns, PRO can take its
reference from an antecedent:
– John1 dressed himself1
– John1 thinks Mary likes him1
– John1 wants [PRO1 to be loved]
• However, it has special referential
properties of its own
– Subject/Object control
• John1 promised Bill [PRO1 to be good]
• John persuaded Bill1 [PRO1 to be good]
– Obligatory/Arbitrary control
• John1 tried [PRO1/*2 to sing]
• [PROarb to sing now] would be inappropriate
The distribution of PRO:
the PRO theorem
• PRO is an NP
• But its distribution is not the same as a
typical NP:
•
•
•
•
I saw him
I spoke to him
He left
* I tried [him to sing]
•
•
•
•
* I saw PRO
* I spoke to PRO
* PRO left
I tried [PRO to sing]
• At first sight it seems that PRO cannot
appear in a Case position (it is an
exception to the Case Filter)
• But there are non-Case positions where
PRO cannot go either
– * John’s picture PRO
– * John is very fond PRO
• So the restriction on the distribution of
PRO is more stringent
Government
• Government is a relationship between certain
elements (governors) and certain positions:
– Governors = lexical heads (N, V, P and A) and
finite Inflection
– Governors govern complement and specifier
positions:
•
XP
spec
X’
X
comp
• Case assigners are governors
• (but not all governors are Case assignors)
• So the set of all Case positions is a subset
of the set of all governed positions:
Governed positions
Case positions
• PRO must be ungoverned
• Therefore it cannot appear in a Case
position
Governed positions
Case positions
PRO
Explaining the PRO theorem
• Anaphors (reflexive pronouns and NP
traces) must have a close by antecedent
– John1 admires himself1
– * John1 thinks [Mary admires himself1]
– John1 was admired t1
– * John1 was believed [Mary to admire t1]
• Pronominals (personal pronouns) cannot
have a close by antecedent:
– * John1 admires him1
– John1 thinks [Mary admires him1]
• Pronominals don’t have to have
antecedents at all (anaphors do):
– He left
– * himself left
• There is a part of the structure which
contains (at least) the pronoun and a
governor
= the governing category
• Binding theory
– A: an anaphor must be bound in its governing
category
– B: a pronominal must be free in its governing
category
• Bound = coindexed with an appropriate
antecedent
• Free = not bound
• So pronominals and anaphors are in
complementary distribution
• (Controled) PRO is like an anaphor
– Because it must have an antecedent
• (Arbitrary) PRO is like a pronominal
– Because it does not need an antecedent
• So PRO is a pronominal anaphor
• So PRO must be bound and free in its
•
•
•
•
governing category
But this is a contradiction!!!
The contradiction can be solved if PRO has
no governing category
PRO will have no governing category if it is
not governed
Hence the PRO theorem
A typology of empty categories:
Overt
+ pronominal
- pronominal
+ anaphor
*
himself
- anaphor
him
John
Covert
+ pronominal
- pronominal
+ anaphor
PRO
NP-trace
- anaphor
**
Wh-trace
* doesn’t exist because all (overt) NPs must have Case and
therefore must be governed
** exists, but not in English: missing subject of finite clause
in e.g. (most) Romance languages, Slavic languages,
Semitic languages, Hungarian, etc.