Transcript Slide 1

1
Euthanasia
I
2
Some Background:
Voluntary
Involuntary
Passive
Voluntary
Passive
Euthanasia
Involuntary
Passive
Euthanasia
Active
 What is euthanasia?
Voluntary
Active
Euthanasia
Patient consent.
Involuntary
Active
Euthanasia
No patient
consent.
Involve withholding or
taking the patient off
live-preserving
treatments.
Involve giving the
patient a life-ending
“treatment”.
3
Some Background:
 Why might someone request or perform
euthanasia?
 What ethical positions might one take on
euthanasia?
4
James Rachels: “Active and Passive Killing”
Rachels’ Project
• Rachels argues that the American Medical Association’s
distinction between active and passive killing is ethically
unfounded.
• Note that Rachels’ paper was published in a medical journal,
not a philosophical journal.
5
American Medical Association Doctrine (244):
The intentional termination of the life of one human being by
another—mercy killing—is contrary to that for which the
medical profession stands and is contrary to the policy of the
American Medical Association.
The cessation of the employment of extraordinary means to
prolong the life of the body when there is irrefutable evidence
that biological death is imminent is the decision of the patient
and/or his immediate family. The advice and judgment of the
physician should be freely available to the patient and/or his
immediate family.
6
American Medical Association Doctrine:
• “extraordinary means”: ‘any procedure or intervention which
in the judgment of the attending physician would serve only
to postpone artificially the moment of death.’ (North Carolina
legal definition)
• “imminent”: within a week? within six months?
According to Rachels:
• The AMA doctrine forbids “active euthanasia”.
• The AMA doctrine permits “passive euthanasia”.
7
Case 1: Throat Cancer Patient
A patient is dying of incurable throat cancer, and is in
terrible pain, which can no longer be alleviated.
• He is certain to die within a few days, even if present
treatment is continued.
• But he does not want to go on living for those few days
since the pain is unbearable.
• As such, the patient asks the doctor to put and end to it,
and his family joins in the request.
8
Case 1: Throat Cancer Patient
• Suppose the doctor agrees to withhold treatment, as the
AMA doctrine says he may.
• The justification for his doing so is that the patient is in
terrible agony, and since he is going to die anyway, it
would be wrong to prolong his suffering needlessly.
• But if one simply withholds treatment, it may take longer
for the patient to die, and he is sure to suffer more than he
would if direct action were taken in the form of a lethal
injection.
• In this case, endorsing passive euthanasia over active
euthanasia leads to more suffering, and this is in direct
opposition to the humanitarian impulse that fuels the
original decision not to prolong his life.
• The AMA doctrine is essentially cruel!
9
Case 2: Down’s Syndrome Baby
Some Down’s syndrome babies are born with congenital
defects, such as intestinal obstructions, which require
surgery if they are to live.
• Intestinal surgery is relatively routine, but sometimes the
parents and the doctor will decide not to operate, and to
let the child die.
• Ultimately, the child will die of dehydration and infection
over the course of hours or days.
• The AMA doctrine says that this is allowable, where giving
the baby a lethal injection to end its life without suffering is
not.
10
Case 2: Down’s Syndrome Baby
The AMA doctrine leads to life-and-death decisions made
on irrelevant grounds.
• The reason that the relatively simple intestinal operations
are not performed is clearly that the child has Down’s
syndrome, and the parents and doctor judge that because
of that, it is better to let the child die.
• But it is the intestinal obstruction and not the Down’s
syndrome that risks killing the child. The issue of the
intestinal blockage is essentially irrelevant to the issue of
why the parents are letting the child die.
• According to this way of thinking, if there is an intestinal
blockage, it is permissible to let the child die, but if there
were no such blockage, one must not “kill” it.
• Surely that it leads to such life-and-death decisions made
on irrelevant grounds is a strike against the AMA doctrine!
11
Smith & Jones Thought Experiment:
Is there a moral difference between killing and letting die?
Smith stands to gain a large inheritance
should anything happen to his six-yearold cousin.
• One evening, while the child is taking a
bath, Smith sneaks into the bathroom
and drowns the child.
• Then Smith arranges things so it will
look like an accident.
12
Smith & Jones Thought Experiment:
Jones also stands to gain a large
inheritance should anything happen to
his six-year-old cousin.
• Jones sneaks into the bathroom,
planning to drown the child in the bath.
• However, when he enters, he sees the
child slip and hit his head, falling
face-down in the water.
• Jones is delighted! He stands by, ready
to push the child’s head back under
if necessary, but it isn’t
necessary.
• With only a little thrashing about,
the child drowns all by himself,
“accidentally,” while Jones does
nothing.
13
Smith & Jones Thought Experiment:
The only difference in the cases is that Smith killed the child,
whereas Jones “merely” let the child die.
• Did either man behave better, from a moral point of view?
• If the difference between killing and letting die were a
morally important matter, we should say that Jones’
behavior was less morally reprehensible than Smith’s.
• But both men acted from the same motive (personal
gain), and had the same end in view.
• And the consequence of each situation was the same.
• If Jones pleaded, “But I didn’t kill him; I just let him die,”
we wouldn’t give this any weight.
• But if there was some moral difference, we should.
14
Killing vs. Letting Die
The fact that most cases of euthanasia are not motivated by
greed, nor do they involve the deaths of normal healthy
children, does not change the fact that there is no moral
difference between killing and letting die.
• The AMA policy focuses on the crucial issue of “the
intentional termination of the life of one human being by
another.”
• But the AMA policy denies that the cessation of treatment
is the intentional termination of a life.
• But what is the cessation of treatment but the intentional
termination of a life?
• If it weren’t the intentional termination of a life, what would
be the point of it?
15
Killing vs. Letting Die
One reason why so many people think there is an important
moral difference between killing and letting die is that most
actual cases of killing are clearly terrible, and most actual
cases of letting die seem motivated by humanitarian
reasons.
• We learn to associate killing with people with morally
reprehensible motives, and letting die with doctors trying
to alleviate their patients’ suffering.
• But the difference between these cases is one of
motivation, not one about the acts themselves.
16
Killing vs. Letting Die
Standard claim distinguishing killing from letting die:
“The important difference between active and passive
euthanasia is that, in passive euthanasia the doctor
does not do anything to bring about the patient’s death
[…] In active euthanasia, however, the doctor does
something to bring about the patient’s death: he kills
him.” (246)
• It is inaccurate to say that, in passive euthanasia, the
doctor does nothing. He does something very important:
he lets the patient die.
17
Killing vs. Letting Die
• In moral terms, inaction is a kind of action.
• You might insult someone by not shaking their hand.
• You might make someone believe you are dead by not
moving.
• You might starve your pet to death by not feeding it.
• If a doctor knowingly lets a patient die who was suffering
needlessly from an easily-curable illness, the doctor
would be blameworthy, just as he would be if he had
needlessly killed the patient.
• Just like Jones, it wouldn’t do him any good to stand by
the defense that he “didn’t do anything.” For not doing
anything is precisely what killed the patient.
18
Morality and the Law
• Whether a patient died as a direct result of his disease, or
as a result of a life-ending treatment can make an
important legal difference.
• But this should not make an important moral difference.
• Ultimately, the law forces upon medical professionals a
moral doctrine than may be indefensible, and which will
have considerable effect on their practices.