Lecture 2. Compensation and responsibility

Download Report

Transcript Lecture 2. Compensation and responsibility

Lecture 2. Compensation and
responsibility
Erik Schokkaert (KULeuven,
Department of Economics)
Structure
1.
2.
3.
Responsibility and compensation in a quasilinear model: optimal income redistribution
in a first best setting
Another application: distribution mechanism
(prospective financing mechanisms) in the
health care sector
From first best-solutions to social orderings
1. Responsibility and compensation in a
quasi-linear setting (BOSSERT en FLEURBAEY,
Social Choice and Welfare, 1996)
Responsibility and compensation



the responsibility cut: (aiR, aiS)
EIER (equal income for equal R): full
compensation
ETES (equal transfer for equal S): strict
compensation
An impossibility and a possibility


Th 1. In general, EIER and ETES are
incompatible.
Th. 2. If the pre-tax income function is
additively separable in C- and S-variables,
then, there is a natural solution satisfying
both EIER and ETES
How to proceed from here?
IMR
WIMR
ETES
GSS
WGSS
EIER
EIUR
EIRR
X
ETUS
ETRS
Strengthening and relaxing EIER
GSS => WGSS => EIER => EIUR => EIRR
Strengthening and relaxing ETES
IMR => WIMR => ETES => ETUS => ETRS
Characterizations
IMR
GSS
X
WGSS
X
EIER
X
EIUR
EIRR
WIMR
X
X
X
ETES
X
X
X
ETUS
ETRS
The egalitarian-equivalent solution
IMR
GSS
X
WGSS
X
EIER
X
EIUR
EIRR
WIMR
X
X
X
pre-tax income she would
earn with reference talent
ETES
X
X
X
ETUS
ETRS
EE
uniform transfer to satisfy the budget
contraint
The conditional-egalitarian solution
IMR
GSS
X
WGSS
X
EIER
X
EIUR
EIRR
CE
WIMR
X
X
X
responsibility part
ETES
X
X
X
ETUS
ETRS
EE
"guaranteed income"
Characterizations
IMR
GSS
X
WGSS
X
EIER
X
EIUR
X
EIRR
CE
WIMR
X
X
X
ACE
ETES
X
X
X
ETUS
X
AEE
ETRS
EE
average over all levels of
talent
responsibility part
average over all levels of
effort
2. Designing prospective financing
schemes in the health care sector

Incentive problems in health care - examples:



Two "extreme" solutions:



reimbursement of expenditures (e.g. fee for service)
prospective financing
Trend towards prospective financing and
benchmarking:



financing of hospitals or practices of doctors
financing schemes for regions and sickness funds
advantage: incentives for cost control
danger: incentives for risk selection
Solution? Risk adjustment
EXAMPLE 1: REGIONAL DISTRIBUTION MECHANISM
Central government
Financial
contribution
Citizen
Subsidy
Regional authority
Local "health" tax?
EXAMPLE 2: REGULATED COMPETITION WITH RISK
ADJUSTMENT
Solidarity fund
Solidarity
contribution
Premium
subsidy
Managed care
organisation
Consumer
Premium
Contribution
Basic idea



In practice: risk-adjusted premium subsidies
often derived from observed expenditures
In principle: risk-adjusted premium subsidies
based on “acceptable costs”: “costs generated in
delivering a specified basic benefits package,
containing only medically necessary and costeffective care” (Van de Ven and Ellis, 2000)
Therefore: many factors, which do have an
influence on observed expenditures, should
NOT be used for calculating the risk-adjusted
premium subsidies

QUESTIONS:


what variables should be included in the RAsystem?
how to design a prospective financing system?
Reinterpretation of the Bossert-Fleurbaey
model (Schokkaert, Dhaene, Van de Voorde, HE 1998;
Schokkaert and Van de Voorde, JHealth Econ 2004)


health care expenditures: x i  f (a i )
total amount of premium subsidies:
ω (=  i)
i

monetary gain made on a patient i:

responsibility cut:
i  i  x i
C R
x i  f (a i , a i )
"Cost efficiency"

NEUTRALITY: for any two individuals i and j
with a iC  a Cj , i   j

C
consequence: i, j : a i
it holds that
i   j
C R
 a j , ai
R
 aj
"Solidarity"

NO INCENTIVES FOR RISK SELECTION:
for any two individuals i and j with
R
ai
R
 a j , i
consequence:
it holds that

 j
i, j : a iR  a Rj , a iC  a Cj
i   j
Theorems

Proposition 1. If the medical expenditure
function can be written (i ) as
C R
C
R
f (a i , a i )  g(a i )  h(a i )
then the following mechanism satisfies NIRS
and NEUT:


C
C
i   g(a i )   g(a k )
n
nk
NOTE. If    x i , then
i
i  g(a iC ) 

R
h
(
a

k)
nk
An impossibility result

Proposition 2. If the medical expenditure
function is not additively separable in the
variables aC and aR, then NO risk adjustment
scheme can satisfy both NIRS and NEUT.
Alternative solutions?

Keep NIRS, drop NEUT: egalitarianequivalent solutions

Keep NEUT, drop NIRS: conditionalegalitarian solutions
Empirical illustration:
-
individual data for 321,111 Belgian insured
(no self-employed)
-
RIZIV-reimbursements for 1995 (medicines
are not included)
per capita reimbursed health expenditures:
38.299 BEF (949 Euros)
-
a. treatment of omitted variables

the conventional approach neglects the
effects of the R-variables in x i  f (a iC , a iR )

therefore, the estimates of the effects of the
C-variables are biased, if there is correlation
between C- and R-variable
b. non-separable specifications

introduction of multiplicative effects in the
specification:



age * loyalty to general practitioner
medical supply * disability
no longer additively separable: conditional
egalitarian approach introduces incentives for
risk selection
A general remark


it is possible to neutralize the effect of
responsibility variables for the computation of
the premium subsidies
advisable to distinguish explicitly two stages:


do the econometric work as carefully as possible
– specify the best explanatory model
set up an explicit discussion about the ethical (or
political) choices
3. From first best to social
orderings: Fleurbaey (2005)

BASIC ASSUMPTIONS:



rejection of welfarism: subjective satisfaction is
not the ultimate criterion ("responsibility for
subjective happiness")
rejection of perfectionism: preferences of the
population should be respected
reducing income inequalities is good, provided
this has no adverse consequences on health
Some notation




every individual has a particular healthconsumption bundle zi = (hi , ci ). Perfect
health denoted by h*.
every individual i has well-defined monotonic
preferences Ri over these bundles
how to define social preferences R over
allocations z = (z1,…,zn )?
social preferences will depend on population
profile of individual preferences, hence R(R)
Feasible allocations



every individual i is endowed with a mapping
wi (hi ), defining her income after all taxes
and transfers except health-related ones
every individual is endowed with a mapping
mi (hi ), describing how much of medical
expenses must be made in order to bring her
to health state hi
individual budget constraint:
ci  w i (h i )  Ti  mi (h i )  Si
ci  (  ) w i (h i )  (  )mi (h i )
Pareto-principle and independence
RESPECT OF INDIVIDUAL PREFERENCES
BASE SOCIAL PREFERENCES ON INDIVIDUAL PREFERENCES
IN A VICINITY OF INDIVIDUALS' CURRENT SITUATION
Pigou-Dalton condition (revised)


traditional Pigou-Dalton condition makes
sense only in a unidimensional world
not care much
cares a
lot about
extension todoes
multidimensional
setting
may
about health
health
come in conflict with the Pareto condition
RESTRICT APPLICATION OF PIGOU-DALTON PRINCIPLE
TO SITUATIONS WHERE THE TWO INDIVIDUALS HAVE THE
SAME PREFERENCES OR ARE BOTH AT A PERFECT HEALTH
LEVEL
"FULL-HEALTH EQUIVALENT INCOMES"
In normal circumstances
Relationship with WTP?



full-health equivalent consumption = actual
consumption – "sacrifice" for better health
willingness-to-pay = "sacrifice" for better
health + productivity gain due to better health
if productivity gain = 0, then
FHEC = Actual consumption - WTP